Contradictions and Conundrums in Gun Prohibition
by Patrick L. Lilly
[email protected]
Special to The Libertarian Enterprise
There are three great misconceptions about anti-gun laws which hardly
ever get mentioned. It is no surprise that they are passed over by
those advocating such laws, but it is somewhat surprising that many
of those who answer such proposals usually miss, and fail to point
out, these three glaring flaws in all "gun control"(1) proposals.
First, "gun prohibition" is a more accurate description of all such
laws and proposed laws than "gun control." Such laws don't "control"
anything in any meaningful sense. They are, pure and simple
"prohibition," in the classic sense of America's disastrous alcohol
prohibition. They make simple possession of something a violation of
law, in and of itself.
But even this term subtly misstates the case. At least in theory,
alcohol prohibition could have been enforced on everyone in
America, and obeyed by everyone in America, specifically
including those who enforced it. There was no necessity for the cops
going in to destroy other people's barrels of beer to have beers in
their own back pockets. Indeed, it could be cogently argued that
genuine teetotalers would be more likely to be honest enforcers of
alcohol prohibition than those who would really like to have a drink
themselves.
No such thing is true about gun prohibition, however. For this
reason, a more descriptive term might be gun discrimination.
Anti-gun possession laws must all have built into them at the most
fundamental level an exception for those who enforce
laws-indluding the anti-gun laws. So they implicitly contain a sort
of self-contradiction. Far from "getting rid" of guns, anti-gun laws
merely divide society into two strata, with a yawning gulf between
them: an upper class of the armed elite, employed by the government,
who can defend themselves, and a much larger lower class,
composed of all the rest of us, who cannot defend ourselves-at
least not legally. Worse, once the elite sees that the underclass
cannot defend itself, they realize that they (the elite) can not only
defend themselves, they can commit crimes against the
underclass, and do so with utter impunity. A quick look at history
shows that this realization is never long in coming.
Put simply, the conundrum implicit in all gun prohibition is this:
Gun prohibition is enforced by people with guns. It is not, as
it obviously cannot be, enforced by people without guns. It does not,
cannot, disarm everybody. It isn't meant to. The main problem
that this causes is not, as opponents of gun prohibition too
often rush to claim, that it leaves the disarmed masses at the mercy
of those among them who manage to get away, at least temporarily,
with disobeying such laws and keeping guns themselves for the purpose
of committing random crimes. The main problem it causes is
that it leaves the legally-created underclass at the mercy of the
elite class, who most definitely are not breaking the "law,"
who are not armed only temporarily, until they are discovered,
but, rather, are armed permanently, and who, therefore, are
perfectly free to commit crimes against members of the underclass,
not randomly, but on a systematic, institutionalized, and perpetual
basis. The main purpose, and effect, of "gun control" is not to
prevent the average person from defending his life, liberty and
property against random crimes committed by self-employed criminals.
Its main purpose and effect is to prevent the average person from
defending himself, his home, and his family against the armed
government elite-better known as the police and the military.
The practical point is this: No matter how "bad" you may think guns
are (and no matter why), they have already been invented, and the
genie simply cannot be put back in the bottle. The question is not
whether there will be guns or not. It is only whether everyone
(or, at least everyone who wants to) will have them, or only
some people will have them. Those who back anti-gun laws
implicitly sign on to the principle of only some people having them.
That means that they implicitly sign on to the principle of most
people-which strangely enough, often includes those people
themselves-being left completely at the mercy of the elite they
create.
The second great misconception of gun prohibition proponents is that
they are backing non-violence, and creating a less violent world. Gun
prohibition-like all prohibition-is violence, and its
imposition creates more violence, not less. It is, implicitly
and irretreiveably, unprovoked, pre-emptive, aggressive violence
against people who have not harmed anyone. It is nothing but the most
ludicrous of self-contradictions for a person to assert, on the one
hand, that he or she is a non-violent person, or, worse yet, a
pacifist, and then, on the other hand, to promote gun prohibition.
When you promote gun prohibition, you are overtly and unambiguously
supporting gun violence against innocent people. In
this vein, the oft-repeated claim of gun grabbers that various other
countries, which have even more draconian anti-gun ownership laws
than the U.S., have "less violence" than we do should never be
answered with pointless arguing over statistics. It should be
answered with the fact that they certainly do have violence,
and gun violence at that; it's just that the violence works so
well and so pervasively that it doesn't happen out on the streets
where the news media can easily cover it. Instead, it happens behing
jail and prison walls, and in the offices of tax collectors. But it
is no less violence for being indirect and harder to see.
Note well: this is not a metaphor, nor is it any kind of
hyperbole or exaggeration. The enforcement of gun prohibition
consists of nothing but the use of guns to attack, without the
slightest real provocation, people who have committed no violation of
anyone's real rights. Putting the gun in someone else's hand, someone
who you believe, rightly or wrongly, is acting in your stead and for
your interests, does not get you off the moral hook. When you
recommend that the police be sent out, with guns, to jail, or
kill, others simply for having guns -- and this is, of course,
the essence of all gun prohibition laws -- you are putting your stamp
of approval on such aggressive violence, and you are just as guilty
of gun violence as if you held the gun in your own hands. When you
make such a proposal, you no longer have any business calling
yourself a pacifist, or a supporter of non-violence; you are
proposing nothing other than the pre-emptive use of violence to
accomplish your chosen social and cultural goals.
Those who react to every outbreak of violence, such as the recent
shootings in Littleton, with knee-jerk calls for more gun
prohibition, have been far too successful at controlling the debate,
and keeping it firmly away from points like these. Instead, they
delude people into debating pointless points like whether or not
"guns kill people," and perfectly real but irrelevant statistics. But
experience to this point should be sufficient to convince anyone
interested in retaining what little is left, and reclaiming the much
larger volume that has already been lost, of our gun rights, that he
or she is only playing into the hands of the prohibitionists by
taking such bait and even bothering to discuss such points.
It doesn't matter whether it is the guns, or the people
holding them, who may properly be said to be "killing people," and
it's high time that this was pointed out. It doesn't matter
how many burglars get shot for every accidental gun-cleaning death,
or for every homeowner who otherwise get injured or killed with his
or her own gun. It doesn't matter whether or not
"criminals"(2) buy guns at gun shows. It doesn't matter
whether anyone "needs" (whatever that means) a bigger ammunition clip
or not. It doesn't matter whether or not levels of crime
committed by self-employed criminals go down where government-allowed
concealed carrying laws are enacted. It doesn't even matter whether
the authors of the Second Amendment sought to bestow on us (or, more
properly, protect) an individual right as opposed to a collective
right to "keep and bear arms" or not.
What does matter is that gun prohibition puts the people at
the mercy of the government and its police, which is just what they
want, and why the police establishment now universally supports more
and ever more gun prohibition. (This wasn't always the case, but
that's because police were once actually interested in preventing and
controlling crime, instead of committing crimes themselves.) What
does matter is that gun prohibition laws-all of them,
no matter how written, or at whom they are aimed (pun intended), or
how-are in and of themselves, improper, because they
contradict themselves, because they violate the principle (not the
Constitutional clause) of equal protection, because they divide
society into the legal haves and the legal have-nots, and because
they can never be enforced except by always putting more, and more
deadly, weapons into the hands of government agents, pointed at the
rest of us. It is high time that defenders of gun rights begin
answering the (deliberately) misleading arguments of gun prohibition
enthusiasts with fundamental points of principle like these,
instead of falling into their rhetorical traps.
The last great misconception, of course, is the idea, implicit in all
gun prohibition proposals, that the promoters actually have a
right to decide whether or not they will allow other
people to possess things. The simplest way to cut through the forest
of red herrings and get back to debating principles is to
point out, first, last, and always, that, no matter what you think
about guns, or about gun owners, it is simply not up to you
whether or not you will respect their right to own honestly acquired
property-guns or anything else. Seeing gun prohibition flaps in their
most general terms, as property rights issues, eliminates any
necessity to delve into the details of guns, gun design, ammunition,
crime statistics, or any of the other irrevelancies which prohibition
advocates throw up to obscure this more fundamental issue.
Respecting other people's rights, even if you don't like them or
don't trust them, is simply not optional. Nor it is
conditional, coming and going with the flux of statistics of societal
conditions. On the contrary, it is universal. Leaving other people
alone, until and unless they actually intrude on your rights in some
way, is the one obligation which you, like everyone else, owe to your
fellow man or woman a priori, whether you like it or not. And
this applies no matter how violent you think society has become (and
even if you're right), no matter how deadly guns have become, no
matter how many of them there are, no matter how many homicides there
were last year, no matter how many accidental shootings there were
last year, and no matter how inconvenient you think it is for you --
even if you're right. Anyone who "just decides" that he doesn't have
to respect his neighbors' property rights any longer, because he
feels threatened or for any other reason, is making a big, big
mistake. It's not just a practical mistake, it's a moral and
legal mistake, and it makes the person who decides it into a
criminal himself, not a crusader against crime, or against violence.
(1) This term is, of course, a euphemism. Gun rights advocates have
always tried to avoid it, and substitute more realistic descriptions,
and rightly so. Indeed, one can look at it as substantial progress
that, more and more frequently, the term "prohibition" is being used
in the public debate. As noted, however, virtually any possible
substitute term has drawbacks of one kind or another. This is partly
because such a wide variety of sorts of violations of individual
rights are subsumed under this general title.
(2) References to "criminals" in such contexts are often exercises in
the fine art of tautology, and should be promptly exposed as such.
Most often, the people obliquely referred to are "criminals" only
because they are violating, or trying to violate, gun prohibition.
But too often the gun grabbers get away with biasing the discussion
by implying that they are talking about bank robbers, rapists, or
muggers. Half the trick of coming off well against a gun
prohibitionist is usually cutting through his or her misdefinition of
the terms in which the debate is carried out (See (1) above).